Knowledge Only Policy
1 Introduction
This website is unique in recognising
that debate cannot produce knowledge; that debate-derived policy is thus
belief-only; but that ‘knowledge’ has not been definitively differentiated from
‘belief until now.
As a first attempt at this differentiation, we might tentatively consider that
disharmony, violence, revolution and war arise when debate-derived belief-only
policy fails in the reality which it ignores, while craftsmanship, science and
technology are accepted harmoniously without debate by their success in the
reality which they incorporate as knowledge; that were the debate-derived
belief-only policies which result in the former to be replaced with knowledge
as exemplified by the latter, all forms of disharmony might be avoided; and
that while voter alienation is likely to grow with accumulation of belief-only
policy failures, accumulation of knowledge-only policy successes is likely to
create voter enthusiasm for prioritising their implementation.
As to the failure of debate-derived policy, we might recall that Socrates
attributed it to the rhetorical tricks of debaters and the gullibility of
voters, rather than to the failure of belief-only debate itself, while Plato
believed this failure in reality to be eliminated by rational thought applied
to an Ideal Beyond rather than from sense-perception of our reality; that Plato
thus believed in non-reality; and that while philosophers such as Mill et
al believed full adult suffrage to be the guarantor of successful
policy, its continuing failure under just such suffrage is now the cause of
voter alienation, knowledge-only policy not having been recognised until now as
the only guarantor of success in reality.
Having thus identified the absence of knowledge as the source of belief-only
debate and related it to the futility of all such debate since time immemorial,
subsequent text to this and other sections will amplify this relationship.
Meanwhile, to terminate debate-derived belief-only policy, section 2 presents
my definitive differentiation of the knowledge/belief dichotomy as the
foundation of my Campaign for Knowledge-Only Policy and on this foundation,
section 3 invites readers to join this Campaign. However, for those who wish to
read more before joining, sections 4 – 26 supply additional text to clarify the
scope of this differentiation and the universal benefit of adopting it. Thus,
subsequent text for these and additional sections will amplify the need for and
benefit of adopting knowledge-only policy in all fields currently lacking it,
my intention being to have it adopted universally and globally.
2 Knowledge of Reality
For knowledge-only policy to be
possible, knowledge must be definitively differentiated from belief. To this
end, I recognise that reality stimulates the human imagination to rational
beliefs transformable to positive or negative knowledge by evaluation of their
compliance or non-compliance with reality, or to those which can only be
accepted, rejected or suspended as beliefs beyond reality-evaluation in
practice or in principle, but which cannot be accepted as knowledge.
Thus, this differentiation shows that while beliefs can be reality-validated to
positive knowledge or reality-refuted to negative knowledge, debate of
opinion/counter-opinion is merely debate of belief/ counter-belief supported by
partially-selected facts/counter-facts, neither set of which amounts to
debate-terminating knowledge; that debate-derived belief-only policies thus
fail in reality by being incompatible with reality; that knowledge-only policy
succeeds in reality by being compatible with it; that success is preferable to
failure; that knowledge-only policies ought thus to eliminate their belief-only
alternatives; and that enthusiastic participation ought thus to eliminate
alienation as soon as voters are offered knowledge-only policies to prioritise
for implementation within known resource limits.
Thus, subsequent text to this and other sections will show how the
presence/absence of my co-defined reality-evaluation definitively
differentiates the knowledge/belief dichotomy and with it those of truth/
falsehood, wisdom/folly, right/wrong and good/bad; and how adoption of this
means of differentiation ought to ensure knowledge-only policy success rather
than belief-only-only policy failure c.f. sections 14 – 18).
3 Invitation to Readers
In light of sections 1 and 2, this
section invites readers to tell others of their acceptance of my now definitive
differentiation of the knowledge/belief dichotomy in numbers sufficient to make
politicians record their acceptance that knowledge rather than belief must now
be the preferred source of policy; and that while ‘knowledge’ and ‘belief’ have
thus far been more or less synonymous in all languages, the presence or absence
of my now co-defined reality-evaluation not only differentiates the
knowledge/belief dichotomy, but also those of truth/falsehood, wisdom/folly,
right/ wrong and good/bad with the clarity to ensure that ‘they speak of little
else at the Dog and Duck’.
However, given that acceptance of this invitation may need further exposition,
my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that knowledge, truth,
wisdom, right and good, all work in reality and are thus definitively and
objectively different from belief, falsehood, folly, wrong, and bad which do
not work in reality; that my newly defined reality-evaluation of beliefs as
specific hypotheses, has been the sole source of the knowledge which is our
craftsmanship, science and technology, and of the knowledge-content of our
traditional behaviour codes to the extent of their having secured our survival
since time immemorial by harmonising our innate selfishness with our innate
need for hierarchical social cohesion as the group-species we are; and that
this harmonisation has never been complete and thus needs all acquirable
relevant knowledge rather than more belief/counter-belief.
Again, to reinforce the need for readers to tell others of their acceptance of
this invitation, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that
debate of belief/counter-belief produces only a transient belief-consensus;
that the failure in reality of such belief-consensus has always resulted in
disharmony, violence, revolution or war; and that this will stop only when
knowledge replaces belief, reality being the only secure basis for
decision-taking (c.f. sections 4, 5, 10, 14 – 18 and 22 – 26 in particular).
4 Mistake Avoidance
This section will emphasise that the
campaign for knowledge-only policy is not a campaign for
adjustment of belief-consensus by addition of new facts/counter-facts to any
debate of opinion/counter-opinion. It is a campaign for
universal acceptance of my newly defined reality-evaluation as the sole means
of ensuring that knowledge is not mistaken for belief or vice versa; that
knowledge is not mistakenly rejected to sustain debate of
belief/counter-belief; that debate itself is terminated by reality-evaluation
of belief and counter-belief to positive or negative knowledge; and that
knowledge-only policy thus created will reverse voter-alienation.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show where and how
conclusive knowledge is ignored and/or deliberately unsought in order to derive
party-political or pressure-group advantage from belief-consensus adjustment
through continual debate; where and how the main belief/counter-belief debate
is suspended in favour of debating derivative beliefs/counter-beliefs more
likely to be thus mistakenly advantageous; where and how supposedly supportive
facts and counter-facts are merely re-assertions of belief/counter-belief; and
where and how belief-consensus is mistakenly claimed to be knowledge (c.f.
sections 1 – 3).
5 Inconclusiveness of Debate
This section will show that while
debate airs belief/counter-belief with reference to whatever facts/
counter-facts might be available in the absence of conclusive knowledge, any
resulting belief-consensus must thus remain inconclusive; that while early
philosophers such as Socrates and Plato recognised this inconclusiveness, they
were mistaken in seeking conclusiveness through clarification of the meaning
and use of words; in relying on rationality alone, in rejecting sense-perceived
reality, and in thus failing to differentiate knowledge from belief in any
realistic manner; that later philosophers mistakenly believed debate to be
sufficient, provided the resulting consensus was open to the widest possible
suffrage; but that modernism now denies the possibility of conclusiveness in
mistakenly accepting elective relativism of belief/counter-belief as the best
we can expect to achieve.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will cite objective
knowledge of reality as the terminator of all belief/counter-belief debate and
my newly defined reality-evaluation as the means by which metaphysics, epistemology,
political philosophy and all non-observational/non-experimental fields can be
seen to be mistaken in their reliance on rationality alone (c.f. sections 1-
4).
6 Craftsmanship
In light of section 2, this section
will show that the imagination of early man was successively stimulated by
reality to believe that some action by him might benefit him, and that by
acting on this belief and observing the result he would learn whether or not it
was beneficial. Thus, for example, he might have believed that a stake driven
into the ground would stand vertically, that he might drive it in with his
fist; that by acting thus he was reality-evaluating his belief to knowledge;
that subsequently he might have believed that a heavy stone would be better
than his fist and so on; and that such early transformations of
reality-stimulated beliefs to knowledge were the dawn of the craftsmanship and
of the recognition of cause-effect relationships which since time immemorial
have made our survival increasingly comfortable.
Thus my subsequent text to this and other sections will exemplify the role of
reality-evaluation in the development of craftsmanship from the hunter-gatherer
through the agricultural to the urban stages of social development; from the
recycling of non-edibles such as bone, skin, fur and feather through the
weaving of vegetable fibres and construction in wood and stone to the metals of
the bronze age and beyond, none of which would have been achieved other than by
the reality-evaluation of initiating belief to knowledge, whatever else might
have remained belief in its absence (c.f. sections 1-5).
7 Science
In light of section 2 this section
will show that the scientific method, first fully introduced by Galileo, was
the method by which hypotheses (beliefs) as to the cause-effect parameters of
natural phenomena could be reality-evaluated by experimentation designed to
eliminate all but one possible cause of the effect being investigated; that for
such as Karl Popper, C. P. Snow and their followers, the scientific method was
thus mistakenly believed to be the collection of evidence in support of
parameter correlations for which no cause-effect relationships had been
established by experimentation; that while this mistake enabled them to claim
openness-to-refutation as the defining characteristic of science and thus
mistakenly to believe its knowledge valid only until further evidence is
collected, they made no reference to the Galilean experimentation which is the
defining characteristic of cause-effect science which though expandable by
additional knowledge is never thus refutable; that this mistaken belief led in
turn to that of conflating/eliding science with relativist philosophy; that
while C.P. Snow believed his ‘two cultures’ to be science and art, he failed
otherwise to define either and thus failed to recognise both as knowledge, art
being craftsmanship; and that he thus joined the neo-Platonists who
conflate/elide knowledge with their self-styled rational belief and are thus
anti-science and pro-pseudoscience.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will correct this
misunderstanding of science and its method of knowledge acquisition, a
misunderstanding which was circulated by Galileo’s contemporary, Descartes; by
Francis Bacon, a founder of the Royal Society; and by many of its Fellows even
today (c.f. sections 1- 6).
8 Pseudoscience
In light of section 2, this section
will show that pseudoscience omits experimentation as to whether or not its
correlated parameters are cause and effect; that accordingly its correlations
are meaningless, however statistically analysed or mathematically modelled;
that pseudoscience can be detected wherever debate is employed to generate a
belief-consensus; that once thus detected, it is best ignored; but that it
nonetheless persists because its proponents focus public attention on the
alleged consequences of its conclusions rather than on the manner by which they
were reached. Thus, for example, while the Natural Selection of Darwinism
lacked experimental justification, it survives as a theory because public
attention has been focussed on its mistakenly alleged consequences for
religious belief and anti-religious disbelief.
Again, this section will show that belief in ship-source releases being the
cause of species-extinction/ ecological-disaster, persists only because its
proponents distract public attention from the non-toxicity of the resulting
concentrations in seawater; that belief in the alleged consequences of
anthropogenic global warming persists only because its proponents distract
public attention from the photosynthesis and biodegradation which continuously
recycle carbon dioxide through the atmosphere and the entire biomass of land
and sea; from the localised oxygen-depletion which interrupts this
biodegradation to produce fossil fuels; and from the Urey reaction and its
reversal by the volcanism of tectonic plate movement which continuously recycle
carbon dioxide through the atmosphere and carbonate rock.
Yet again, this section will show that hypotheses as to
species-extinction/ecological-disaster arising from ship-source releases to the
marine environment were reality-refuted by experimentation in the 1970s as
confirmed by their absence at any actual incident; that hypotheses as to the
rates of abstraction and release of carbon dioxide by biological and geological
processes separately or interactively have yet to be reality-evaluated; and
that consequently the public is misled to expect anthropogenic global warming
from combustion of part of a fossilisation but for which all of its carbon
dioxide equivalent would already be recycling through atmosphere, biomass and
carbonate rock, especially while increased concentrations of carbon dioxide in
controlled atmospheres are already known to produce higher crop yields by more
photosynthesis from proportionately more carbon dioxide in these atmospheres.
However, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that belief in
species-extinction/ ecological-disaster though reality-refuted, still persists
in thwarting the reality-validated knowledge which would otherwise restore the
marine environment to its pre-release state more quickly and cost-effectively
than belief-only regulation currently permits; that belief in anthropogenic
global warming needlessly raises energy costs; that belief in recycling causes
costs to exceed the values recovered; and that knowledge-only policy requires
science to replace pseudoscience in general (c.f. sections 1 -7).
9 Collusion in Creating and Adjusting Belief-Consensus
This section will show that far from
recognising the need for knowledge to replace belief, political parties collude
in adjusting belief-consensus through debate to the extent which permits them
to take turns in government; that they thus prefer the flexibility of belief to
the rigidity of knowledge; but that the reality thus ignored eventually
overwhelms such belief-only collusion in yet another outbreak of disharmony,
violence, revolution or war in response to the accumulating failures of
belief-only policy .
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that while voting
ought be retained to prioritise knowledge-only policy options for
implementation within known resource limits, voting on belief-only policy
options ought be conditional on knowledge being recognised as unavailable pro
tem; on belief being recognised as very likely to fail in reality; and
on democracy itself being recognised as ultimately sustainable only if
knowledge-only policy options replace those of belief-only, whenever and
wherever possible (c.f. sections 1 – 8).
10 Transience of Belief-Consensus
This section will show that from
earliest times self-selected or group-selected leaders have relied on
belief-consensus created by the debating and voting of councillors and
advisors; that these were initially such as tribal elders; priesthoods,
senates, aristocracies etc; that these are now cabinets, back-benchers,
pressure-/focus-groups and the individual voters of democracies; but that no
belief-consensus can be other than transient in the absence of the conclusive
knowledge of reality which would terminate the debate which otherwise
transiently adjusts belief-consensus from debate to subsequent debate.
Again, with Socrates having noticed the transience of belief-consensus from one
debate to the next; with Plato having attempted to terminate debate by reliance
on rationality alone; and with nobody since having differentiated the
knowledge/belief and associated dichotomies as I now have, this section will
show for the first time that political history is merely a sequence of
belief-consensual responses to belief-consensual failures; that the
success/failure ratio of such response is much less than the heads/ tails ratio
of coin-tossing; that the failure of belief-only policy has not previously been
recognised as reality-refutation of its initiating belief; and that such
failure will continue until it is recognised as negative knowledge to be
replaced with positive knowledge as soon as possible.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will collectively show the
need to replace belief with knowledge wherever and whenever possible (c.f.
sections 1 – 9).
11 History as Belief-Consensus Failure Uninfluenced by Knowledge-Only Success
Having shown in sections 9 and 10
that human groupings have responded to the challenges of each successive
belief-consensus failure with another belief-consensus despite all of them
being more or less failures, this section will show that human groupings have
nonetheless failed to replace belief-consensus with knowledge of humanity which
would have successfully prevented these challenges or would have successfully
responded to them; and that human groupings have failed to extend the
knowledge-content of their traditional behaviour codes to this end by
reality-evaluating hypotheses progressively derived from them, despite
contemporaneously extending the knowledge which is craftsmanship, science and
technology by reality-evaluating hypotheses progressively derived from them.
Thus, my subsequent text to this section and others will show that the parallel
sequences of our belief-only failures and of our knowledge-only successes were
independent, the reality-evaluations of the latter being absent from the
former, rather than being applied across the full spectrum; but that far from
doing so now, we are actively rejecting the knowledge already available from
our traditional behaviour codes, craftsmanship, science and technology in our
unquestioning acceptance of arbitrary beliefs in equality, freedom and rights
as professed by pseudoscience in general and by its economic, environmentalist,
educationalist and sociological expressions in particular (c.f. sections 1 –
10).
12 Inadequacy of Belief-Consensus
This section will show that while
historians now attribute social progress to successive implementations of
non-religious beliefs in equality, freedom and rights, nobody has previously
explained why these implementations have not yet eliminated disharmony,
violence revolution and war; that while united kingdoms, united republics or
indeed attempts at world government through such as the League of Nations and
the United Nations are intended to avoid all such disturbance, nobody has
previously explained why such ‘unifications’ have not yet succeeded and indeed
have always failed; and that while enthusiasts bemoan the existence of Security
Council vetoes, nobody has explained how the UN itself could exist without
them, given the preference for localised belief-consensus over universal
knowledge-application, despite the mayhem associated with reality’s eventual
overthrow of belief-consensus, however wide-ranging initially.
Thus, my subsequent text to this section and others will show that belief-only
democracy is possible only so long as some sort of belief-consensus can be
maintained; that such is more difficult within a collection of states and is
yet more difficult across the world as a whole; that with all state policies
being belief-only and with any belief-consensus being more acceptable in one state
or union than in another or indeed being unacceptable in others, no attempt has
previously been made to resolve belief-only conflict by reality-evaluation of
belief/counter-belief to positive or negative knowledge; that in the absence of
such resolution the only remaining options are vetoed stalemate, tolerance of
difference, or conflict; that whatever is believed about social progress and
peaceful coexistence, ‘the strong do as they wish and the weak suffer as they
must’ as Thucydides stated in reporting the Peloponnesian War (431 – 404 BC);
and that my Campaign for Knowledge-Only Policy to prevent or resolve belief-only
conflicts is consequently long overdue. (c.f. sections 1-11).
13 Futility of Debating Opinion/Counter-Opinion
This section will show that no
democratic commentator on the current ills of the world has previously done
other than offer his or her opinions counter to other opinions in the hope of
adjusting debate towards one or other belief-consensus or to overthrow one by
another through pro tem voting; that such commentators never
allude to the absence of conclusive knowledge nor to the need to acquire it;
that they are so far from rejecting belief, as to be substituting it for the
knowledge-content of traditional behaviour codes and for the knowledge which we
already have from science and its associated technology; and that through
pseudoscience they have begun mistakenly to conflate/elide beliefs with
knowledge while even nominal scientists now concur rather than to call for more
knowledge to be acquired as to our self-reality, to our external-reality in
general, and to our environment in particular.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will ask whether our future
is to be the continuous failure of debate-derived belief-consensus and
pseudoscience, or the continuous success of knowledge acquisition by
reality-evaluation of beliefs as specific hypotheses (c.f. sections 1 – 12).
14 Knowledge Contrasted with Three Categories of Belief
To dispel the obscurantism which now
seeks to conflate/elide belief with knowledge in pseudoscience’s futile
attempts to resolve conflicting beliefs (opinions), this section now
differentiates knowledge from three categories of belief by noting, with
reference to section 2, that Category A belief is transformable to specific
hypotheses for reality-validation or reality-refutation to positive or negative
knowledge by direct observation or by observing the results of designed
experimentation; that Category B beliefs are inaccessible to reality-evaluation
in principle or pro tem practice and thus cannot be
transformed to knowledge whether positive or negative; that Category C beliefs
persist despite having been reality-refuted; and that no belief can thus be in
rational conflict with knowledge.
Again, with reference to section 2, this section now defines the Ur-belief in
knowledge as our belief in ourselves and external world being knowable and
which accordingly gives rise to the hypotheses of Category A while itself
remaining suspended in the unlikelihood of our being able to create hypotheses
as to the ultimate nature of reality let alone of our being able to build the
experimentation equipment needed to reality-evaluate them. Yet again, this
section now defines the Ur-belief of religion as our awareness of the
ultimately unknowable, the specific derivatives of which can only be accepted,
rejected or suspended, or if touching on the reality of human nature, can be
submitted to reality-evaluation as hypotheses of Category A or consigned to
Category C as already reality-refuted. Furthermore, this section now defines
the Ur-belief in rationality as that which must be rejected as mistaken belief
in the acquisition of knowledge without reality-evaluation, though its
derivatives can be submitted to reality-evaluation as hypotheses of Category A
or consigned to Category C as already reality-refuted, while rationality itself
develops mathematics and logic from reality-validated axioms or earlier
reality-validated knowledge.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will confirm that conflict
arises only between belief and counter-belief; and that it never arises between
belief and knowledge except in the irrationality of madness (c.f. sections 1 –
13).
15 Knowledge-Content of Traditional Behaviour Codes and of Religion per se
In light of section 2, this section
will show that reality-evaluation of beliefs as specific hypotheses not only
produced the knowledge which is craftsmanship, science and technology, but also
our self-knowledge of human nature which is the knowledge component of
traditional behaviour codes; that this self-knowledge, though now widely
decried as out-dated religious belief, is reflected in ethics, literature and
political philosophy to the extent to which these harmonise our innate selfishness
with our survival-dependent need for social cohesion as the group-species we
are; but that the as yet undifferentiated belief-contents of these codes
continue to cause disruption and violence counter to this survival.
Again, this section will show that while some derivatives of the religious
Ur-belief reflect this self-knowledge as reality-validated by their capacity to
provide emotional support and to inspire, motivate and encourage
survival-supportive behaviour, others are counter to this survival as
reality-refuted by their capacity to produce social disharmony, segregation,
violence, revolution and war. Yet again, this section will show that acceptance
of this self-knowledge as belief by the religious and its rejection as belief
by the anti-religious is a mutual rejection of reality; that our concepts of
good/bad and of right/wrong, reflect this self-knowledge of what is
conducive/non-conducive to our survival; that our conscience and sense of
fairness are our innate acceptance of responsibility for this survival; but
that our knowledge-based socially cohesive survival nonetheless continues to be
threatened by the collusive knowledge-rejecting beliefs of political/religious
leaders and their respective supporters.
Accordingly, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that my
definitive differentiation of knowledge/belief and associated dichotomies of
truth/falsehood wisdom/folly right/wrong and good/ bad can resolve all
conflicts of belief/counter-belief (c.f. sections 1 – 14).
16 Absence of Knowledge in Anti-Religious Belief
In light of sections 2 and 14, this
section will show that the anti-religious rely solely on the rational Ur-belief
in rejecting the knowledge-content of traditional behaviour codes as religious
belief, while replacing it with their own arbitrary beliefs in equality,
freedom and rights; that all anti- and non-religious belief per
se is thus devoid of the reality-evaluation which produced the
previously undifferentiated knowledge-contents of traditional behaviour codes,
ethics and political philosophy; that all such religious, anti-religious and
non-religious beliefs must now be reality-evaluated in the contexts of their
intended fields of implementation as hypotheses of Category A; and that in
moulding social policy to beliefs devoid of prior reality-evaluation, the anti-
and non-religious show themselves to be anti-knowledge in their retention of
beliefs consignable to Category C by their observed failure on implementation
in reality.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that all
derivatives of my defined Ur-belief in rationality, require reality-evaluation
prior to implementation; and that my definition of reality-evaluation replaces
epistemology, makes metaphysical-knowledge oxymoronic, and reclassifies social,
political, economic and many more modernist fields as pseudoscience replaceable
with science by submitting their respective beliefs to the reality-evaluation
which converts belief to positive or negative knowledge (c.f. sections 1 – 15).
17 Differentiation of Previously Undifferentiated Mixtures of Knowledge and Belief
In light of sections 2 and 14 – 16,
this section will show that literary and dramatic works previously analysed for
the formerly undefined truth of their content and the formerly undefined
artistry of their presentation can now be analysed for their capacity to
inspire, motivate and encourage survival-related behaviour by their reflections
of my now defined self-knowledge of humanity, and for their capacity to provide
emotional satisfaction through the artistry which I now define as
craftsmanship; that religious texts and dramatic ceremonials have not
previously been analysed in this way; that the belief/counter-belief debate or
open conflict among the religious and between them and the anti-religious
mistakenly accepts as belief the reality-validated knowledge-content common to
all behaviour codes, while failing to reality-refute their belief-contents as
being disharmonious and anti-survival, and while refusing to accept, reject or
suspend as personal preference, all beliefs beyond reality-evaluation in
principle.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that religious
and non-religious texts have thus far been undifferentiated mixtures of knowledge
and belief, no matter how much the contestants deny it; that the
knowledge-content can be differentiated from the belief-content of traditional
behaviour codes as in the previous paragraph, while the Ur-belief of
religion per se is itself a refection of human desire and as
such is reality-validated by its relief of loneliness and its support of
survival-related social behaviour even when the belief beyond ultimate
reality-evaluation is merely suspended; that anti-religious disbelief bereft of
this reflected knowledge neither relieves nor supports, even when the disbelief
beyond ultimate reality-evaluation is accepted; and that life or death
conflicts of belief/ counter-belief beyond reality-evaluation in principle are
expressions of irrational madness whether the believer is religious or
anti-religious (c.f. sections 1 – 16).
18 Rational Impossibility of Knowledge-Belief Conflict
Having contrasted the
knowledge-content of religion per se with the absence of
knowledge-content in its disbelief in sections 14-17, this section will show
that no rational conflict can arise between knowledge and Category A beliefs
(hypotheses) which become positive or negative knowledge by their
reality-evaluation. Nor can conflict arise between knowledge and Category C
beliefs already reality-refuted. Again, conflict cannot arise between knowledge
and the religious Ur-belief of category B because it and its derivatives are
beyond reality-validation or reality-refutation in principle, while both
religious and non-religious beliefs of Category B which touch on the reality of
human behaviour or of our environment in general can be allocated as hypotheses
to category A for reality-evaluation of their positive or negative effects on
social harmony or environmental welfare in general or to category C as already
reality-refuted by their failure on implementation in the reality of either or
both.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that beliefs have
intrinsic value only as hypotheses for reality-evaluation and thus provide no
grounds for dispute let alone life-or-death conflict; that believers, whether
religious or anti-religious, have thus far avoided this no-contest resolution
by knowledge, only because belief and knowledge were undifferentiated until my
third book was published in early 2010; that they must now recognise
belief/counter-belief whether religious or non-religious to be the only source
of conflict; and that the way to avoid or resolve all such conflict is to
reality-evaluate belief to positive or negative knowledge wherever the belief
pertains to reality, and to accept, reject or suspend peacefully all beliefs
beyond reality-evaluation in principle as matters of personal choice (c.f.
sections 2 and 14 – 17 in particular).
19 Previously Missed Opportunities for Knowledge/Belief Differentiation
This section will show that the
opportunity to differentiate the dichotomies of knowledge/belief, truth/
falsehood, wisdom/folly, right/wrong and good/bad was missed by
hunter-gatherers, early craftsmen and law-givers because having no written
records of the means (reality-evaluation) by which their culturally transmitted
knowledge had been acquired, they simply believed it to have been gifted by the
gods of the beyond, together with mathematics and indeed Creation itself; that
it was again missed by Renaissance man who simply followed Plato in believing
knowledge to be produced by rational interaction with his ideal beyond; that it
was yet again missed by Enlightenment man who expanded his belief in
rationality alone, despite the then recent development of the scientific method
(reality-evaluation) by which hypothetical beliefs were being converted to
knowledge of cause-effect and expressed mathematically.
Thus, with those interested in cause-effect science being always vastly
outnumbered by those interested in their self-styled rational beliefs, this
section will show that nobody differentiated craft-knowledge from the
hypothetical beliefs from which it had been derived by the reality-evaluation
of direct observation since time immemorial; and that nobody differentiated our
self-knowledge from the hypothetical beliefs from which it had been derived by
the reality-evaluation of direct observation over the same timescale. However,
while it will show that our self-, craft-, scientific-, and
technological-knowledge was independent of self-styled rational belief prior to
the so-called Enlightenment, it will also show that far from differentiating
knowledge from belief, the self-styled enlightened conflated-elided them with
their self-styled rationality to the extent of permitting such as Darwin,
Huxley and subsequent Darwinists to exclude cause-effect experimentation and to
rely on the arbitrary parameter correlations which now typify pseudoscience;
that this pseudoscience has since been transmuted to the relativism which now
denies the existence of objective knowledge to the detriment of science in
general; and that this regression started because earlier opportunities to
differentiate the knowledge/ belief dichotomy had been missed, or even ignored
for self-serving ends.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will provide more examples
and more details of the instances and consequences of this longstanding failure
to differentiate knowledge from belief (c.f. sections 1 -18).
20 Erroneous Argumentation against Knowledge/Belief Differentiation
This section will show relativism to
have arisen from rationalists erroneously arguing that religious belief was
incompatible with science; that Darwin had shown science to be superior to
religion; that science and anti-religion were synonymous; that the rationalism
common to both was the source of all Enlightenment progress; that religious
belief was irrational and consequently the source of all benighted regression;
but that while Darwin was the greatest scientist ever, science changed with
time as did all products of rationality; that change itself was the only
constant; that all rational belief was thus relative; that rational debate was
thus the only valid means of creating and changing belief-consensus and of
deciding which debated policy-option would be implemented; that elective
democracy was thus the pinnacle of human achievement; and that the democratically
derived political situation at any time was the only reality requiring further
rational consideration.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that such
argumentation returns us to the debate of belief/counter-belief which has
produced the policy failures which currently alienate voters in the continuing
absence of the conclusive knowledge which modernists believe to be
inaccessible; and that while belief-only democracy fails to avoid disharmony,
violence, revolution and war, knowledge-only democracy has never existed. (c.f.
sections 1 – 19).
21 Science Contrasted with Pseudoscience
In recalling that the knowledge which
is craftsmanship was created by reality-evaluation of hypothetical beliefs by
direct observation of cause and effect, this section now notes that in his work
the craftsman manipulates his tool as cause and observes its effect on the work
piece until his successive causes have had the overall effect of completing the
intended artefact for its useful or decorative function; that craft-like direct
observation of nature by such as Aristotle produced the beginning of what I
define as descriptive science; that nonetheless the cause of the effect which
is a natural phenomenon cannot always be known by direct observation; and that
something more is needed to investigate cause and effect in general. Thus, this
section now notes that while Aristotle believed bodies to fall at speeds
dependent on their weights, Galileo treated this belief as a hypothesis for
evaluation by designed experimentation; that he was thus the first to know them
to fall at speeds independent of weight but with an acceleration, from which
knowledge he was able to explain the motion of bodies in general whether they
be free-falling objects, projected cannon balls, or swinging pendulums; that
from this Newton was later to explain the motion of the moon; that scientific
cause-effect knowledge is thus produced only by experimentation designed to
permit quantified causes to have observable quantified effects expressible
mathematically; that this approach enables quantified effects to be predicted
from quantified causes; and that this is the basis of all physicochemical
science and of all sciences based upon it.
In contrast, this section now also notes that pseudoscience is belief not yet
reality-evaluated by direct observation or by designed cause-effect
experimentation; that instead, it selects an effect, attributes a cause and
proceeds to correlate variation of the one with variation of the other regardless
of the limitless number of others which would also have such numerical
correlations with either or both; that nonetheless, statistics are cited in
justification of such arbitrarily selected correlations; but that while the
statistics per se may be unimpeachable, the correlation is no
less arbitrary than the initial selection of cause-effect parameters. Indeed,
even supposing these parameters were cause and effect, the statistical
analysis per se would not necessarily tell which was which.
Again, this section notes that sustaining belief in such correlations often
involves rejection of existing knowledge or refusal to reality-evaluate the
belief for fear of thus refuting it; and that the resulting belief-based
policies are sustained solely by the pseudoscience to which their failures are
attributable though never so attributed, as is now possible, by noting the
absence of my newly defined reality-evaluation..
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will show that
pseudoscience-inspired belief-only policies fail in economics,
environmentalism, education, welfare, child protection, criminology, drug
use/misuse, medicine, psychology etc; and that all such failure is
avoidable by replacing pseudoscience with science; with commonsense as now
defined as knowledge traditionally/culturally available to all; or with
positive knowledge derived from reality-evaluation of pseudoscience, having
rejected its beliefs as thus identified negative knowledge (c.f. sections 1 –
20).
22 Need to Replace Belief with Knowledge
Readers of this website should by now
have agreed on the need to implement knowledge-only policy instead of its
belief-only alternatives. However, before proceeding to my subsequent texts in
support of the above sections, readers might reinforce their agreement by
listing for themselves the current policy areas which are other than abject
failures, thus revealing by the shortness of the list the extent of the need
for our Campaign for Knowledge-Only Policy and of the need to encourage others
to support it.
Again, before proceeding to my further supportive texts, readers might reflect
on the extent to which belief (as now defined) requires external authority
whether it be canonical or secularly legislative; on the ability of knowledge
(as now defined) to speak for itself when given the opportunity to do so; on
the extent to which belief-only legislation now invades fields previously
managed by tradition and commonsense; on the thus achievable nature of our
Campaign; and on the effort needed to advance it being little more than to
spread its acceptance by directing others to this website.
Meanwhile, my subsequent text to this section and others will reinforce this
need, for the further satisfaction of which I will add further sections and
supportive text as may be found helpful in further promotion of this Campaign
for Knowledge-Only Policy.
23 Means Adequate to Need
This section now shows that the need
to change from belief to knowledge in policy formulation will not be satisfied
by participating in belief/counter-belief debate; that this need will be
satisfied only by terminating all such debate by reference to its futility as
reality-validated by the current failure rate of belief-consensus
implementations; that knowledge or recognition of the need for its further
acquisition are the only means by which debate and its failures can be
terminated in practice; that the relevant knowledge can be acquired only by
reality-evaluating contending beliefs/counter-beliefs or more likely by
reality-evaluating hypotheses derived from existing knowledge to acquire the
new knowledge needed to refute the said beliefs; and that while these needs
have never been previously satisfied, they will continue to be unsatisfied
unless alienated voters and rebelling politicians support this Campaign for
Knowledge-Only Policy.
Thus, my subsequent text to this section will show how and where this Campaign
has already delivered its intended results and how and where it may next be
expected to deliver them most quickly by the means outlined in these and future
sections (c .f. sections 3, 22, and 26).
24 Means Obstructive of Need
This section will show that those
most adept at the creation and adjustment of belief-consensus are those whose
education consisted in learning how to compare, contrast and construe any
contention placed before them; that neither they nor their educators ever do
other than treat beliefs/counter-beliefs in this way by citing
facts/counter-facts without being aware of the need for or the absence of
conclusive knowledge; that in doing so they learn to make rhetorical references
to rational/irrational, to real/unreal and to the dichotomies of
knowledge/belief, truth/falsehood, wisdom/folly, right/wrong and good/bad
without ever recognising the need to define any of them, let alone the need for
a definition which embraces all of them; that having graduated in the ability
to gain and retain facts and in the ability to compare, contrast and construe
them, they enter politics to run the country, the civil service to advise
politicians how to run it, or the media to comment on how it is being run; and
that in doing so, they do no more than they did in writing their school and
university essays. Indeed even those who join the political establishment to
make a difference through their previous acquisition of relevant professional
knowledge, are initially surprised at the ease with which such knowledge is
ignored by politicians, administrative civil servants, and media commentators
all of whom have a vested interest in the continuous debate of
belief/counter-belief to party- or self-advantage.
Thus, my subsequent text to this and other sections will note this adherence to
belief/counter-belief and emphasise the pressing need to bypass it to apply
existing knowledge or to acquire new knowledge, it being a proud boast of the
administrative generalist that he/she can take decisions on any matter without
any personal knowledge whatsoever. Again, my subsequent texts will identify
commentators who serve our purpose by delineating the failures of the political
establishment without ever suggesting how they might be avoided or corrected
and who thus self-identify as possible supporters of this Campaign for
Knowledge-Only Policy instead of simply remaining supporters of belief-only
changes which by being acceptable to one or other set of political-party
beliefs might prove acceptable to supporters in sufficient numbers to keep one
party in power or to replace it with another, such being the only discernable
objective of political comment thus far (c.f. sections 5, 9 – 13, and 19 – 23).
25 Timeliness of Our Campaign for Knowledge-Only Policy
This section will show that while
voters are becoming alienated from party-politics, members of parliament are
becoming alienated from their own cabinets, shadow cabinets and respective
whips; that these alienations are confirmed by decreasing turn-outs at local
and general elections and by the non-party voting patterns of individual
members of parliament; that some members are beginning to cite this development
as confirming a rebirth of democracy freed from party restraint; and that
commentators are beginning to foresee this rebirth leading to the election of
individuals on the basis of their own manifestos with the house then voting
freely on any and every issue as it arises. However, while widening alienation
increases the timeliness of our campaign for party manifestos to be based on
knowledge-only and for elective voting to prioritise knowledge-only policies
for implementation within known resource-limits, this timeliness is further
enhanced by any moves to extend democracy beyond the beliefs of individual
voters to those of individually voting politicians thus creating even more
belief-derived failure-ridden chaos than we already have.
Accordingly, subsequent text to this section will emphasise the need and
timeliness for party-specific policies to be knowledge-only and for their
prioritisation to be by general suffrage followed by party-voting in
parliament, these commentator-discerned developments making knowledge-only
policies even more essential than they already are. Thus, subsequent texts to
this section will emphasise the need and timeliness of this Campaign (c.f.
sections 5, 10, 13 and 22 in particular).
26 Further Inducements to Campaign for Knowledge-Only Policy
While the current failure of
belief-only policies within the UK would have been sufficient inducement for
this Campaign for Knowledge-Only Policy without the prospect of an increased
rate of future failures, this section will recall that these policies have also
initiated our involvement in a unification of Europe, and a de-unification of
the UK prior to possible re-unification with Europe; that already alienated
voters are thus being asked to support belief-inspired failures at
ever-increasing scales; that in addition, western belief-only democracies are
showing increasing tendency to intervene in the internal affairs of others to
export a belief-only democracy from which its own electorates are being
increasingly alienated and to which intended recipients have no more than a
belief/counter-belief response; and that, accordingly, the inducement to join
this Campaign for Knowledge-Only Policy has become universal.
Further to this universal dimension, this section will show that knowledge-only
policies will resolve problems which otherwise can only worsen; that knowledge
unifies the human family; that belief/ counter-belief divides it; that the
knowledge/belief and associated dichotomies are easily differentiated by noting
the presence/absence of my newly defined reality-evaluation; that knowledge is
thus easily identified for universal and peaceful acceptance; that beliefs are
equally easily identified for reality evaluation and that
beliefs/counter-beliefs beyond reality-evaluation in principle are easily
identified for universal and peaceful acceptance, rejection or suspension
according to personal preference within all religious and secular communities.
Thus, subsequent text to this section will show that the knowledge which is craftsmanship,
science and technology is universally and peacefully acceptable to all; that
all including west and east, democrat and non-democrat, religious and
non-religious have yet to differentiate knowledge from belief and science from
pseudoscience by the presence or absence of the reality-evaluation defined
herein; and that when one country adopts this peaceful knowledge-only approach
to policy, it will be emulated as universally as was and is knowledge-only
craftsmanship science and technology (c.f. sections 3, 13, 22 and 23).